12

UNCONSCIOUS MIND PRIOR TO FRUED:
The term “unconscious “was coined by the 18th-century German romantic philosopher Friedrich Schelling and later introduced into English by the poet and essayist Samuel Taylor Coleridge.
The unconscious mind (or the unconscious) consists of the processes in the mind that occur automatically and are not available to introspection. It  include thought processes, memory, affect, and motivation. Even though these processes exist well under the surface of conscious awareness they are theorized to exert an impact on behavior.
Paracelsus is credited as the first to make mention of an unconscious aspect of cognition in his work Von den Krankheiten ("About illnesses", 1567), and his clinical methodology created a cogent system that is regarded by some as the beginning of modern scientific psychology. Several concepts of unconscious in his characterizations can be seen in the plays of  William Shakespeare.
Western philosophers such as Espinoza,  Leibniz, A Schopenhauer ,  Fichte, Hegel ,  Kierkegaard, and  Nietzsche, developed a  view of the mind which foreshadowed Freud's theories. Psychologist Jacques Van Rillaer points out that, "the unconscious was not discovered by Freud”.
 In 1890, when psychoanalysis was still unheard of, William James, in his monumental treatise on psychology, examined the way Schopenhauer, von Hartmann , Janet, Binet and others had used the term 'unconscious' and 'subconscious'".
Historian of psychology Mark Altschule observes that unconscious, cerebral activity and  debth psychology were well known to the nineteenth century psychologists and physicians who practiced psychiatry( like Eugene Bleuler and Emil Kraeplein).




The Rediscovery of the Unconscious:
 In the last quarter of the 19th century, as the new science of psychology began to emerge from its roots in philosophy and physiology, consciousness was at the center of the enterprise.

Beginning with Wundt and Titchener, the whole structuralist school of psychology attempted to analyze conscious mental states in terms of their constituent sensations, images, and feelings. Its preferred method of introspection assumed that people had accurate introspective awareness of their own mental states. E.G. Boring summarized the achievements of structuralism with a monograph entitled The Physical Dimensions of Consciousness (1927).

Even William James, opposed as he was to the doctrines of structuralism, embraced a version of introspection as his preferred research method (he had a collection of brass instruments, but he hated using them). James began his Principles of Psychology with the assertion that "Psychology is the science of mental life" . By this he meant conscious mental life -- as he made abundantly clear in the Briefer Course, where he adopted G.T. Ladd’s definition of psychology as "the description and explanation of states of consciousness as such".

At the same time, both James and the structuralists understood that there was more to mental life than was accessible to introspection. The notion that unconscious processes are important elements of mental life is commonly ascribed to Sigmund Freud, the founder of psychoanalysis, but in fact it was an old idea before Freud was even born.

At the beginning of the 18th century, the German philosopher Leibniz had written that our conscious thoughts are influenced by sensory stimuli of which we are not aware:

...at every moment there is in us an infinity of perceptions, unaccompanied by awareness or reflection.... That is why we are never indifferent, even when we appear to be most so.... The choice that we make arises from these insensible stimuli, which... make us find one direction of movement more comfortable than the other.

At the close of that century, Immanuel Kant's Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, the philosopher’s last work and arguably the first comprehensive textbook of psychology, devoted a major section to a discussion "Of the ideas which we have without being conscious of them":

To have ideas, and yet not be conscious of them, -- there seems to be a contradiction in that; for how can we know that we have them, if we are not conscious of them? Nevertheless, we may become aware indirectly that we have an idea, although we be not directly cognizant of the same .

In the 19th century, Herbart, drawing on the views of Leibniz, defined the limen, or sensory threshold, as a mental battleground where various perceptions, themselves mostly unconscious, competed for representation in consciousness.

One of the older ideas can... be completely driven out of consciousness by a new much weaker idea.  On the other hand its pressure there is not to be regarded as without effect; rather it works with full power against the ideas which are present in consciousness.  It thus causes a particular state of consciousness, though its object is in no sense really imagined.

In the Treatise on Physiological Optics, Hermann von Helmholtz argued that our conscious perceptions are determined by unconscious inferences:

The psychic activities that lead us to infer that there in front of us at a certain place there is a certain object of a certain character, are generally not conscious activities, but unconscious ones. In their result they are the equivalent to conclusion, to the extent that the observed action on our senses enables us to form an idea as to the possible cause of this action.... But what seems to differentiate them from a conclusion, in the ordinary sense of that word, is that a conclusion is an act of conscious thought.... Still it may be permissible to speak of the psychic acts of ordinary perception as unconscious conclusions....

The pre-Freudian analysis of unconscious mental life reached its apex with Eduard von Hartmann and his Philosophy of the Unconscious (1868/1931), an extremely popular work whose three volumes, running to more than a thousand pages, went through a total of 12 editions.

For Hartmann, the universe was ruled by the unconscious, a highly intelligent dynamic force composed of three layers: the absolute unconscious, accounting for the mechanics of the physical universe; the physiological unconscious, underlying the origin, evolution, development, and mechanisms of life; and the relative unconscious, which Hartmann considered to be the origin of conscious mental life.


If we now institute a comparison between the Conscious and Unconscious, it is first of all obvious that there is a sphere which is always reserved to the Unconscious, because it remains forever inaccessible to consciousness.
Secondly, we find a sphere which in certain beings only belongs to the Unconscious, but in others is also accessible to consciousness. Both the scale of organisms as well as the course of the world's history may teach us that all progress consists in magnifying and deepening the sphere open to consciousness; that therefore in a certain sense consciousness must be the higher of the two.
Furthermore, if in man we consider the sphere belonging both to the Unconscious and also to consciousness, this much is certain, that everything which any consciousness has the power to accomplish can be executed equally well by the Unconscious, and that too always far more strikingly, and therewith far more quickly and more conveniently for the individual, since the conscious performance must be striven for, whereas the Unconscious comes of itself and without effort.

Hartmann’s "relative unconscious" is what I prefer to call the psychological unconscious – a term referring to those mental states and processes which influence our experience, thought, and action outside phenomenal awareness and independent of voluntary control.

We owe to Hartmann the Romantic notion, still with us in some quarters today, that the unconscious possesses capacities and powers which are superior to those available to consciousness. As Hartmann put it: "the Unconscious can really outdo all the performances of conscious reason".In the end, however, Hartmann’s ideas proved to be too speculative for the first generation of scientific psychologists.

Ebbinghaus, discussing Hartmann’s book, concluded that "what is true is not new, and what is new is not true". William James also offered a warning which would reverberate throughout the 20th century exploration of the unconscious:The distinction… between the unconscious and the conscious being of the mental state… is the sovereign means for believing what one likes in psychology, and of turning what might become a science into a tumbling-ground for whimsies.

James’s criticism was prophetic, as we can see in the ensuing controversy, ranging across the entire 20th century, concerning Freud’s psychoanalytic theory of mental life.

Still, all of this activity, from Leibniz and Kant to Helmholtz and Hartmann, laid the foundation for what Henri Ellenberger, the great historian of psychiatry, called The Discovery of the Unconscious. This discovery was consolidated with what Ellenberger called a new dynamic psychiatry – the psychiatry of Freud, Jung, and Adler.

Based on their clinical observations, for example, Breuer and Freud concluded that the symptoms of hysteria were produced by unconscious memories of traumatic events: "hysterics suffer mainly from reminiscences".

Our observations have shown... that the memories which have become the determinants of hysterical phenomena persist for a long time with astonishing freshness and with the whole of their affective coloring. We must, however, mention another remarkable fact... that these memories, unlike other memories of their past lives, are not at the patients' disposal. On the contrary, these experiences are completely absent from the patients' memory when they are in a normal psychical state, or are only present in highly summary form. Not until they have been questioned under hypnosis do these memories emerge with the undiminished vividness of a recent event.
I shall continue with the unconsciousness related developments in the subsequent decades after Freud and psycho-analytic scholars.
Affectionately,
gandhibabu



 [S1]edit

Comments

Popular posts from this blog