14
Dear
murugappan,
You have asked
me more about unconscious in your reply to my descriptions on them. I
try to give you more elaborations of the same now,
21st century trends in
unconscious studies: implicit memory, implicit perception,
implicit learning, implicit thought, implicit motives and
implicit emotions:
The
rediscovery of the unconscious have
gotten a late start. By early 21 century the increasingly powerful role played by the
concept of automaticity in personality, social, and clinical psychology came to
be published in popular media as well.
The general
argument is that some attitudes, impressions, and other social judgments, as
well as aggression, compliance, prejudice, and other social behaviors, are
typically mediated by automatic processes which operate outside phenomenal
awareness and voluntary control. To some extent, which I have come to think of
as the automaticity juggernaut seems to represent a reaction to a cognitive
view of social interaction which seems, to some, to inappropriately emphasize
conscious, rational, cognitive processes, at the expense of the unconscious, irrational,
emotive, and conative. In addition, the popularity of automaticity seems to
represent a reversion to earlier, pre-cognitive, situationist(relating to the
belief that people are more influenced by external, situational factors than by
internal ones)views within social psychology.
After all,
the concept of automaticity (the ability to do things without occupying the
mind with the low-level details required, allowing it to become an automatic
response pattern or habit. It is usually the result of learning, repetition,
and practice) is at least tacitly(in a way that is understood or implied
without being directly stated) modeled on innate stimulus-response connections
such as reflexes, taxes, and instincts, as well as those acquired through
classical and instrumental conditioning. The automaticity juggernaut is not behaviorism
(learning based on the idea that all behaviors are acquired through
conditioning. Conditioning occurs through interaction with the environment),
because it entails internal mental representations and processes intervening
between stimulus and response, but it is close: if the cognitive processes underlying
social cognition and social behavior are indeed largely automatic, then not too
much thought has gone into them.
HIDDEN
MEMORY:
Like
automaticity, the concept of implicit memory has received a huge amount of
attention in the field. A whole industry has developed around implicit memory,
involving amnesic and demented neurological patients; dissociative disorders
such as psychogenic amnesia, fugue, and multiple personality; children and the
healthy aged; depressed patients receiving electroconvulsive therapy; surgical
patients receiving general anesthesia or conscious sedation; hypnotized
subjects (but apparently not sleepers); and even college students who have all
their wits about them.
Still, there
are some important issues that have to be addressed by further research. For
example, almost all the evidence on implicit memory has been collected within a
single narrow paradigm, repetition priming, leading to theories of implicit
memory which emphasize relatively low-level perceptual processes. But semantic
priming occurs too, not just in posthypnotic amnesia but in organic amnesia as
well, suggesting that these perception-based theories are not adequate to the
phenomenon. Similarly, while explicit and implicit memory are dissociable, they
also interact, requiring revisions in theories which hold that these two
expressions of memory are mediated by separate memory systems in the brain.
Despite
these and other persisting questions, the general acceptance of the distinction
between explicit, conscious and implicit, unconscious expressions of memory
opens the door to extensions of the explicit-implicit distinction to other
domains of mental life.
HIDDEN
PERCEPTION:
Implicit
perception subsumes so-called "subliminal" perception, involving the
processing of stimuli which are degraded beyond conscious perception by low
intensities, brief durations, or masking stimuli. But it goes beyond the
subliminal to include neurological syndromes such as blindsight and neglect,
where the stimuli are in no sense subliminal: they are perfectly visible to
everyone but the brain-damaged subject. So too, in the conversion syndromes of
"hysterical" deafness, blindness, and anesthesia. Similarly, in
hypnotic blindness, deafness, anesthesia, and analgesia, the subjects would be
clearly aware of the stimuli in question were it not for the hypnotist’s
suggestion. On the fringes of consciousness, are cases of so-called pre-attentive
processing, where the stimulus in question is nominally supraliminal, but
escapes focal awareness by virtue of para-foveal presentation, or presentation
over the unattended channel in the dichotic listening or shadowing paradigm.
Thus, the term implicit perception captures a broader range of phenomena than
is covered by the term subliminal perception, because it covers the processing,
outside of conscious awareness, of stimulus events which are clearly
perceptible in terms of intensity, duration, and other characteristics. It also
has the extra advantage of skirting the difficult psychophysical concept of the
limen.
What all of
these phenomena have in common is a dissociation between explicit and implicit
perception, analogous to the dissociation between explicit and implicit memory:
the subject’s experience, thought, and action is affected by some event in the
current stimulus environment, in the absence of conscious perception.
HIDDEN
LEARNING:
Continuing
the elaboration of the explicit-implicit distinction to other domains, we can
define implicit learning as the acquisition of new knowledge and patterns of
behavior through experience, in the absence of awareness of the knowledge or
behavior so acquired. As it happens, the term "implicit learning"
antedates implicit memory.
In some
respects, the learning of artificial grammars appears similar to the acquisition
of syntax in natural language. After all, we are perfectly fluent speakers and
interpreters of our native language long before we learn the rules of grammar
in elementary school. But implicit learning has also been observed in a wide
variety of other paradigms, including classical and instrumental conditioning,
control of complex systems, and the learning of categories and sequential
relationships. In each of these cases, the claim is that people's behavior is
shaped by prior experience – the classical definition of learning -- even
though they are unaware of what they have learned.
As with
implicit perception, however, the border between implicit learning and implicit
memory is a little vague. Of course, this is as it should be: memory provides
the cognitive basis for learning in the first place, and whatever is learned
has to be stored in memory. But the problem goes deeper than that. When normal
subjects learn an artificial grammar, they certainly remember being asked to
study the sample strings, and they may even remember the strings themselves,
even if they are unaware of what they have evidently learned about the
structure of the grammar itself. By contrast, when brain-damaged amnesic
patients acquire new patterns of behavior from experience, they are amnesic for
the whole learning experience. In amnesia, the occurrence of implicit learning
also gives evidence of preserved implicit memory, but I prefer to reserve the
term implicit memory for effects which occur in the absence of conscious memory
for the original experience. By the same token, I reserve implicit learning to
abilities and patterns of response that are acquired through learning
experiences, in the absence of conscious awareness of what has been learned.
There is a
continuing debate over whether implicit learning is really unconscious in any
meaningful sense of the term. It just may be too much to expect subjects to be
able to articulate an entire Markov-process artificial grammar, but subjects
might be consciously aware of just enough of the rule to permit them to
discriminate at above-chance levels between grammatical and ungrammatical
strings. Perhaps this debate will be resolved if we pay a little more attention
to the format in which the newly acquired knowledge is represented. Perhaps, as
implied by the original artificial grammar studies, the subject acquires a
whole system of If-Then productions and this procedural knowledge, like all
procedural knowledge, is inaccessible to conscious introspection. On the other
hand, perhaps the knowledge isn’t procedural at all, but declarative in nature.
For example, subjects might abstract from the learning trials a prototype of a
grammatical string; alternatively, they may simply memorize the instances on
the study list. In either case, they may make relatively accurate
grammaticality judgments by consciously comparing test items to the summary
prototype, or to the specific exemplars they’ve memorized. We just don’t know
yet. But what we do know is that amnesic patients can learn from their experience
without remembering the learning experience itself, and in that sense, at
least, implicit learning gives evidence of unconscious influence.
If the
concept of implicit learning is more controversial than those of implicit
memory or implicit perception, the concept of implicit thought is even more so.
Still, the literature contains some favorable evidence, if only just a little. Accordingly,
I have defined implicit thought as the influence of some cognitive
representation, itself neither a percept nor an episodic memory, on experience,
thought or action, in the absence of conscious awareness of that
representation.
HIDDEN
THOUGHT:
Implicit
thought may well underlie some of the most interesting facets of creative
thought. In this view, intuition reflects a priming-based "feeling of
knowing" similar to what we commonly see in studies of memory; incubation
reflects the gradual accumulation of strength of this primed idea; and insight
reflects the emergence of the pre-conscious idea into the full daylight of
consciousness.
Along with
automaticity, implicit memory, implicit perception, implicit learning, and
implicit thought comprise the cognitive unconscious. But cognition is not all
there is to mental life, and so we are led to ask whether there is an affective
unconscious, and a conative unconscious, as well. Of course, emotional and
motivational states may arise automatically, and in that sense result from
unconscious processes. But can motives and emotions themselves be unconscious,
in the same way that implicit memories can?
HIDDEN
MOTIVES:
In fact, the
late David McClelland and his associates have articulated a concept of implicit
motives – interestingly, without overt reference to the concept of implicit
memory. Explicit motivation might be defined as the conscious representation of
a conative state, or the desire to engage in some particular activity, as
represented by a craving for food, yearning for love, and the like. By
contrast, implicit motivation would refer to any change in experience, thought,
or action which is attributable to one’s motivational state, in the absence of
conscious awareness of that state.
We are
admittedly verging near Freudian territory here, but the motives in question
are not seething sexual and aggressive impulses arising from the id; they are
motives for achievement, power, affiliation, and intimacy. Moreover, explicit
motives are self-attributed: the person is aware of the motive, can reflect on
it, and can report its presence in interviews or on personality questionnaires.
Implicit motives, by contrast, are inferred from the person’s performance .
HIDDEN
EMOTIONS:
Turning to
the affective domain, we seek dissociations between explicit and implicit
emotions. Again paralleling the vocabulary of the cognitive unconscious, we
define explicit emotion as the person’s conscious awareness of an emotion,
feeling, or mood state; implicit emotion, then, refers to changes in
experience, thought, or action which are attributable to one’s emotional state,
in the absence of conscious awareness of that state.
With respect
to the proposition that people can be unaware of emotional states which
nonetheless influence their ongoing experience, thought, and action. Multiple-systems theory of emotion postulates
that every emotional response consists of three components:
-verbal-cognitive,
corresponding to a subjective feeling state such as fear;
-overt
motor, corresponding to a behavioral response such as escape or avoidance;
-and covert
physiological, corresponding to a change in some autonomic index such as skin
conductance or heart rate.
These three
components or systems usually covary, but under some circumstances they can
move in different directions – a state as labeled desynchrony. I am especially interested in a particular
form of desynchrony: in which explicit emotion, as represented by the
conscious, subjective feeling state is absent, but behavioral and somatic signs
of emotion persist. Neuroscientific theory aside, a potentially interesting
approach to implicit emotion has been offered in their application of the
explicit-implicit distinction to the social-psychological concept of attitude. Experimental
approach to implicit emotion is very promising.
The initial
discovery of the unconscious, which was consolidated at the turn of the 20th
century, has been revived, and the process of rediscovery is well along as we
turn to the 21st. In my view, there is incontrovertible evidence for automatic
mental processes and for implicit memories. Implicit perception is, perhaps,
less convincingly established at this point, and implicit learning remains
controversial as well. Still the evidence favoring both concepts cannot be
dismissed out of hand. Research on implicit thought is admittedly immature, but
the evidence in hand is quite provocative.
Based on the
evidence for the cognitive unconscious, implicit motivation and implicit
emotion cannot be dismissed out of hand, but we still require convincing
evidence that they can be dissociated from their explicit counterparts. Still,
it is clear that the paradigms developed in the study of implicit memory
provide a vehicle for exploring all aspects of the psychological unconscious.
In response to Immanuel Kant, we can say that priming and other methodologies
do in fact enable us to infer that that we have ideas, even though we are not
conscious of them. And in response to William James, we can say that these same
methodologies, rigorously applied, will prevent us from believing whatever we
like about the unconscious mind.
In that
respect, I must emphasize that the scope of the psychological unconscious,
broad as it is, does not appear to be so broad as to encompass the unconscious
of psychoanalytic theory. There is no evidence, in any of the science I have
summarized today, favoring Freud’s view that the unconscious is the repository
of primitive, infantile, irrational, sexual and aggressive impulses, repressed
in a defensive maneuver to avoid conflict and anxiety. Nor is there any
evidence to support the more extreme clinical lore concerning unconscious
representations of trauma, or the excesses of the recovered memory movement in
psychotherapy. In this case, as James warned, the unconscious does indeed seem
to be a tumbling-ground for whimsies.
In any
event, the evidence of unconscious mental life is so vast, so convincing,
increasing and strengthening so much with each new issue of our best journals,
that we are in danger of coming full circle, to the position of conscious in essentialism
that Owen Flanagan has discussed. Some philosophers and psychologists have concluded
that automaticity and priming dominate our behavior, so that consciousness is
an illusion -- at best a commentary on what is going on down below, at worst a
delusion that gets in the way of adaptive action (not to mention a proper
scientific understanding of mind and behavior). I think we see this trend
clearly in the "automaticity juggernaut" that I described earlier. As
someone who has devoted virtually his entire career to getting people to take
the psychological unconscious seriously, I am reminded of St. Theresa’s
warning: we should be careful what we pray for, because we just might get it.
As a fervent
supporter of the cognitive revolution in psychology, I am reminded that the
French revolution of 1789 replaced one despotism with another. Is this what we
overthrew behaviorism for: to be told that we are all automatons after all –
that consciousness is a charming feature of human brain activity, but that in
the final analysis it doesn’t buy us anything? I don’t think so. Like language
and intelligence, consciousness is too great an achievement of human evolution
to be useless, much less maladaptive. Consciousness allows us to be aware of
the present, and to reflect on our past, so we can plan for our futures.
Without consciousness there can be no culture – no way of deliberately sharing
our knowledge, experiences, and ideas with others of our species. We now know
that the psychological unconscious is real and dynamically active. But so is
consciousness, and if we ignore this central fact of human existence we will
never achieve a satisfactory science of mental life.
Thus we had
extensive discussion on the unconscious in the modern context. As it says what
Freud could observe was just an iceberg of it. We shall see in out next letter
what he said about unconscious!
Affectionately,
Gandhibabu.
Comments
Post a Comment