24
Dear murugappan,
Empiricism
In both everyday attitudes
and philosophical theories, the experiences referred to by empiricists are
principally those arising from the stimulation of the sense organs—i.e., from
visual, auditory, tactile, olfactory, and gustatory sensation. (In addition to
these five kinds of sensation, some empiricists also recognize kinesthetic
sensation, or the sensation of movement.) Most philosophical empiricists,
however, have maintained that sensation is not the only provider of experience,
admitting as empirical the awareness of mental states in introspection or
reflection (such as the awareness that one is in pain or that one is
frightened); such mental states are then often described metaphorically as
being present to an “inner sense.” It is a controversial question whether still
further types of experience, such as moral, aesthetic, or religious experience,
ought to be acknowledged as empirical. A crucial consideration is that, as the
scope of “experience” is broadened, it becomes increasingly difficult to
distinguish a domain of genuinely a priori propositions. If, for example, one
were to take the mathematician’s intuition of relationships between numbers as
a kind of experience, one would be hard-pressed to identify any kind of
knowledge that is not ultimately empir
Even when empiricists agree
on what should count as experience, however, they may still disagree
fundamentally about how experience itself should be understood. Some
empiricists, for example, conceive of sensation in such a way that what one is
aware of in sensation is always a mind-dependent entity (sometimes referred to
as a “sense datum”). Others embrace some version of “direct realism,” according
to which one can directly perceive or be aware of physical objects or physical
properties (see epistemology: realism). Thus there may be radical theoretical
differences even among empiricists who are committed to the notion that all
concepts are constructed out of elements given in sensation.
Empiricism is the
philosophical stance according to which the senses are the ultimate source of
human knowledge. It stands in contrast to rationalism, according to which
reason is the ultimate source of knowledge. In Western philosophy, empiricism boasts
a long and distinguished list of followers; it became particularly popular
during the 1600's and 1700's. Some of the most important British empiricists of
that time included John Locke and David Hume.
Empiricists Maintain That
Experience Leads to Understanding
Empiricists claim that all
ideas that a mind can entertain have been formed through some experience or –
to use a slightly more technical term – through some impression. Here is how
David Hume expressed this creed: "it must be some one impression that
gives rise to every real idea". Indeed – Hume continues in Book II –
"all our ideas or more feeble perceptions are copies of our impressions or
more lively ones."
Limits of Empiricism
There are many limits to
empiricism and many objections to the idea that experience can make it possible
for us to adequately understand the full breadth of human experience. Another
abstract concept that is difficult to describe from the empirical perspective
is the idea of the self. Which sort of impression could ever teach us such an
idea?
DESCARTES AND RATIONALISM:
Rationalism is a
philosophical movement which gathered momentum during the Age of Reason of the
17th Century. It is usually associated with the introduction of mathematical
methods into philosophy during this period by the major rationalist figures,
Descartes, Leibniz and Spinoza.
Rationalism is any view
appealing to intellectual and deductive reason (as opposed to sensory
experience or any religious teachings) as the source of knowledge or justification.
Thus, it holds that some propositions are knowable by us by intuition alone,
while others are knowable by being deduced through valid arguments from
intuited propositions. It relies on the idea that reality has a rational
structure in that all aspects of it can be grasped through mathematical and
logical principles, and not simply through sensory experience.
Rationalists believe that,
rather than being a "tabula rasa" to be imprinted with sense data,
the mind is structured by, and responds to, mathematical methods of reasoning.
Some of our knowledge or the concepts we employ are part of our innate rational
nature: experiences may trigger a process by which we bring this knowledge to
consciousness, but the experiences do not provide us with the knowledge itself,
which has in some way been with us all along. See the section on the doctrine
of Rationalism for more details.
Rationalism is usually
contrasted with Empiricism (the view that the origin of all knowledge is sense
experience and sensory perception), and it is often referred to as Continental
Rationalism because it was predominant in the continental schools of Europe,
whereas British Empiricism dominated in Britain. However, the distinction
between the two is perhaps not as clear-cut as is sometimes suggested, and
would probably not have even been recognized by the philosophers involved.
Although Rationalists asserted that, in principle, all knowledge, including
scientific knowledge, could be gained through the use of reason alone, they
also observed that this was not possible in practice for human beings, except
in specific areas such as mathematics.
It has some similarities in
ideology and intent to the earlier Humanist movement in that it aims to provide
a framework for philosophical discourse outside of religious or supernatural
beliefs. But in other respects there is little to compare. While the roots of
Rationalism may go back to the Eleatics and Pythagoreans of ancient Greece, or
at least to Platonists and Neo-Platonists, the definitive formulation of the
theory had to wait until the 17th Century philosophers of the Age of Reason.
René Descartes is one of the
earliest and best known proponents of Rationalism, which is often known as
Cartesianism (and followers of Descartes' formulation of Rationalism as
Cartesians). He believed that knowledge of eternal truths (e.g. mathematics and
the epistemological and metaphysical foundations of the sciences) could be
attained by reason alone, without the need for any sensory experience. Other
knowledge (e.g. the knowledge of physics), required experience of the world,
aided by the scientific method - a moderate rationalist position. For instance,
his famous dictum "Cogito ergo sum" ("I think, therefore I
am") is a conclusion reached a priori and not through an inference from
experience. Descartes held that some ideas (innate ideas) come from God; others
ideas are derived from sensory experience; and still others are fictitious (or
created by the imagination). Of these, the only ideas which are certainly valid,
according to Descartes, are those which are innate.
Baruch Spinoza expanded upon
Descartes' basic principles of Rationalism. His philosophy centered on several
principles, most of which relied on his notion that God is the only absolute
substance (similar to Descartes' conception of God), and that substance is
composed of two attributes, thought and extension. He believed that all aspects
of the natural world (including Man) were modes of the eternal substance of
God, and can therefore only be known through pure thought or reason.
Gottfried Leibniz attempted
to rectify what he saw as some of the problems that were not settled by
Descartes by combining Descartes' work with Aristotle's notion of form and his
own conception of the universe as composed of monads. He believed that ideas
exist in the intellect innately, but only in a virtual sense, and it is only
when the mind reflects on itself that those ideas are actualized.
Nicolas Malebranche is
another well-known Rationalist, who attempted to square the Rationalism of René
Descartes with his strong Christian convictions and his implicit acceptance of
the teachings of St. Augustine. He posited that although humans attain
knowledge through ideas rather than sensory perceptions, those ideas exist only
in God, so that when we access them intellectually, we apprehend objective
truth. His views were hotly contested by another Cartesian Rationalist and
Jensenist Antoine Arnauld (1612 - 1694), although mainly on theological
grounds.
In the 18th Century, the great
French rationalists of the Enlightenment (often known as French Rationalism)
include Voltaire, Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Charles de Secondat (Baron de
Montesquieu) (1689 - 1755). These philosophers produced some of the most
powerful and influential political and philosophical writing in Western
history, and had a defining influence on the subsequent history of Western
democracy and Liberalism.
During the middle of the 20th
Century there was a strong tradition of organized Rationalism (represented in Britain
by the Rationalist Press Association, for example), which was particularly
influenced by free thinkers and intellectuals. However, Rationalism in this
sense has little in common with traditional Continental Rationalism, and is
marked more by a reliance on empirical science. It accepted the supremacy of
reason but insisted that the results be verifiable by experience and
independent of all arbitrary assumptions or authority
Rationalism:
Rationalism is the
philosophical stance according to which reason is the ultimate source of human
knowledge. It stands in contrast to empiricism, according to which the senses
suffice in justifying knowledge.
In one form or another,
rationalism features in most philosophical traditions. In the Western
tradition, it boasts a long and distinguished list of followers, including
Plato, Descartes, and Kant. Rationalism continues to be a major philosophical
approach to decision-making today.
Descartes' Case for
Rationalism
How do we come to know
objects — through the senses or through reason? According to Descartes, the
latter option is the correct one.
As an example of Descartes'
approach to rationalism, consider polygons (i.e. closed, plane figures in
geometry). How do we know that something is a triangle as opposed to a square?
The senses may seem to play a key role in our understanding: we see that a
figure has three sides or four sides. But now consider two polygons — one with
a thousand sides and the other with a thousand and one sides. Which is which?
In order to distinguish between the two, it will be necessary to count the
sides — using reason to tell them apart.
For Descartes, reason is
involved in all of our knowledge. This is because our understanding of objects
is nuanced by reason. For example, how do you know that the person in the
mirror is, in fact, yourself? How does each of us recognize the purpose or
significance of objects such as pots, guns, or fences? How do we distinguish
one similar object from another? Reason alone can explain such puzzles.
Using Rationalism as a Tool
for Understanding Ourselves in the World
Since the justification of
knowledge occupies a central role in philosophical theorizing, it is typical to
sort out philosophers on the basis of their stance with respect to the
rationalist vs. empiricist debate. Rationalism indeed characterizes a wide
range of philosophical topics.
How do we know who and what
we are? Rationalists typically claim
that the self is known through a rational intuition, which is irreducible to
any sensorial perception of ourselves; empiricists, on the other hand, reply
that the unity of the self is illusory.
What is the nature of cause
and effect? Rationalists claim that causal links are known through reason. The
empiricist's response is that it is only because of habit that we come to be
convinced that, say, fire is hot.
How do we know which actions
are ethically correct? Kant argued that
the ethical worth of an action can be understood only from a rational
perspective; ethical evaluation is a rational game in which one or more
rational agents envisage their actions under hypothetical conditions.
Of course, in a practical
sense, it is almost impossible to separate rationalism from empiricism. We
cannot make rational decisions without the information provided to us through
our senses, nor can we make empirical decisions without considering their
rational implications.
Affectionately
Gandhiram.
Comments
Post a Comment